One of the formulations of the predicate calculus. Due to the convenient representation of derivations, the sequent calculus has wide applications in proof theory, in the foundations of mathematics and in the automatic search for a deduction. The sequent calculus was introduced by G. Gentzen in 1934 (see [1]). One version of the classical calculus of predicates in the form of the sequent calculus is presented below.
A collection of formulas is a finite set
The axioms of the sequent calculus have the form
In the rules
The sequent calculus is equivalent to the usual form of predicate calculus, in the sense that a formula
is called the cut rule, and the normalization theorem asserts that the cut rule is admissible in the sequent calculus, or that the addition of the cut rule does not change the collection of deducible sequents. In view of this, Gentzen's theorem is also called the cut-elimination theorem.
The symmetric structure of the sequent calculus greatly facilitates the study of its properties. Therefore, an important place in proof theory is occupied by the search for sequent variants of applied calculi: arithmetic, analysis, type theory, and also the proof for such calculi of the cut-elimination theorem in one form or another (see [2], [3]). Sequent variants can also be found for many calculi based on non-classical logics: intuitionistic, modal, relevance logics, and others (see [3], [4]).
[1] | G. Gentzen, "Untersuchungen über das logische Schliessen" Math. Z. , 39 (1935) pp. 176–210; 405–431 ((English translation: The collected papers of Gerhard Gentzen, North-Holland, 1969; edited by M.E. Szabo)) |
[2] | G. Takeuti, "Proof theory" , North-Holland (1975) |
[3] | A.G. Dragalin, "Mathematical intuitionism. Introduction to proof theory" , Amer. Math. Soc. (1988) (Translated from Russian) |
[4] | R. Feys, "Modal logics" , Gauthier-Villars (1965) |
Intuitively, the sequent
[a1] | M.E. Szabo, "Algebra of proofs" , North-Holland (1978) |