In mathematics, specifically algebraic geometry, a scheme is a structure that enlarges the notion of algebraic variety in several ways, such as taking account of multiplicities (the equations x = 0 and x2 = 0 define the same algebraic variety but different schemes) and allowing "varieties" defined over any commutative ring (for example, Fermat curves are defined over the integers).
Scheme theory was introduced by Alexander Grothendieck in 1960 in his treatise Éléments de géométrie algébrique (EGA); one of its aims was developing the formalism needed to solve deep problems of algebraic geometry, such as the Weil conjectures (the last of which was proved by Pierre Deligne).[1] Strongly based on commutative algebra, scheme theory allows a systematic use of methods of topology and homological algebra. Scheme theory also unifies algebraic geometry with much of number theory, which eventually led to Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem.
Schemes elaborate the fundamental idea that an algebraic variety is best analyzed through the coordinate ring of regular algebraic functions defined on it (or on its subsets), and each subvariety corresponds to the ideal of functions which vanish on the subvariety. Intuitively, a scheme is a topological space consisting of closed points which correspond to geometric points, together with non-closed points which are generic points of irreducible subvarieties. The space is covered by an atlas of open sets, each endowed with a coordinate ring of regular functions, with specified coordinate changes between the functions over intersecting open sets. Such a structure is called a ringed space or a sheaf of rings. The cases of main interest are the Noetherian schemes, in which the coordinate rings are Noetherian rings.
Formally, a scheme is a ringed space covered by affine schemes. An affine scheme is the spectrum of a commutative ring; its points are the prime ideals of the ring, and its closed points are maximal ideals. The coordinate ring of an affine scheme is the ring itself, and the coordinate rings of open subsets are rings of fractions.
The relative point of view is that much of algebraic geometry should be developed for a morphism X → Y of schemes (called a scheme X over the base Y ), rather than for an individual scheme. For example, in studying algebraic surfaces, it can be useful to consider families of algebraic surfaces over any scheme Y. In many cases, the family of all varieties of a given type can itself be viewed as a variety or scheme, known as a moduli space.
For some of the detailed definitions in the theory of schemes, see the glossary of scheme theory.
The origins of algebraic geometry mostly lie in the study of polynomial equations over the real numbers. By the 19th century, it became clear (notably in the work of Jean-Victor Poncelet and Bernhard Riemann) that algebraic geometry over the real numbers is simplified by working over the field of complex numbers, which has the advantage of being algebraically closed.[2] The early 20th century saw analogies between algebraic geometry and number theory, suggesting the question: can algebraic geometry be developed over other fields, such as those with positive characteristic, and more generally over number rings like the integers, where the tools of topology and complex analysis used to study complex varieties do not seem to apply.
Hilbert's Nullstellensatz suggests an approach to algebraic geometry over any algebraically closed field k : the maximal ideals in the polynomial ring k[x1, ... , xn] are in one-to-one correspondence with the set kn of n-tuples of elements of k, and the prime ideals correspond to the irreducible algebraic sets in kn, known as affine varieties. Motivated by these ideas, Emmy Noether and Wolfgang Krull developed commutative algebra in the 1920s and 1930s.[3] Their work generalizes algebraic geometry in a purely algebraic direction, generalizing the study of points (maximal ideals in a polynomial ring) to the study of prime ideals in any commutative ring. For example, Krull defined the dimension of a commutative ring in terms of prime ideals and, at least when the ring is Noetherian, he proved that this definition satisfies many of the intuitive properties of geometric dimension.
Noether and Krull's commutative algebra can be viewed as an algebraic approach to affine algebraic varieties. However, many arguments in algebraic geometry work better for projective varieties, essentially because they are compact. From the 1920s to the 1940s, B. L. van der Waerden, André Weil and Oscar Zariski applied commutative algebra as a new foundation for algebraic geometry in the richer setting of projective (or quasi-projective) varieties.[4] In particular, the Zariski topology is a useful topology on a variety over any algebraically closed field, replacing to some extent the classical topology on a complex variety (based on the metric topology of the complex numbers).
For applications to number theory, van der Waerden and Weil formulated algebraic geometry over any field, not necessarily algebraically closed. Weil was the first to define an abstract variety (not embedded in projective space), by gluing affine varieties along open subsets, on the model of abstract manifolds in topology. He needed this generality for his construction of the Jacobian variety of a curve over any field. (Later, Jacobians were shown to be projective varieties by Weil, Chow and Matsusaka.)
The algebraic geometers of the Italian school had often used the somewhat foggy concept of the generic point of an algebraic variety. What is true for the generic point is true for "most" points of the variety. In Weil's Foundations of Algebraic Geometry (1946), generic points are constructed by taking points in a very large algebraically closed field, called a universal domain.[4] This worked awkwardly: there were many different generic points for the same variety. (In the later theory of schemes, each algebraic variety has a single generic point.)
In the 1950s, Claude Chevalley, Masayoshi Nagata and Jean-Pierre Serre, motivated in part by the Weil conjectures relating number theory and algebraic geometry, further extended the objects of algebraic geometry, for example by generalizing the base rings allowed. The word scheme was first used in the 1956 Chevalley Seminar, in which Chevalley pursued Zariski's ideas.[5] According to Pierre Cartier, it was André Martineau who suggested to Serre the possibility of using the spectrum of an arbitrary commutative ring as a foundation for algebraic geometry.[6]
The theory took its definitive form in Grothendieck's Éléments de géométrie algébrique (EGA) and the later Séminaire de géométrie algébrique (SGA), bringing to a conclusion a generation of experimental suggestions and partial developments.[7] Grothendieck defined the spectrum of a commutative ring as the space of prime ideals of with a natural topology (known as the Zariski topology), but augmented it with a sheaf of rings: to every open subset he assigned a commutative ring , which may be thought of as the coordinate ring of regular functions on . These objects are the affine schemes; a general scheme is then obtained by "gluing together" affine schemes.
Much of algebraic geometry focuses on projective or quasi-projective varieties over a field , most often over the complex numbers. Grothendieck developed a large body of theory for arbitrary schemes extending much of the geometric intuition for varieties. For example, it is common to construct a moduli space first as a scheme, and only later study whether it is a more concrete object such as a projective variety. Applying Grothendieck's theory to schemes over the integers and other number fields led to powerful new perspectives in number theory.
An affine scheme is a locally ringed space isomorphic to the spectrum of a commutative ring . A scheme is a locally ringed space admitting a covering by open sets , such that each (as a locally ringed space) is an affine scheme.[8] In particular, comes with a sheaf , which assigns to every open subset a commutative ring called the ring of regular functions on . One can think of a scheme as being covered by "coordinate charts" that are affine schemes. The definition means exactly that schemes are obtained by gluing together affine schemes using the Zariski topology.
In the early days, this was called a prescheme, and a scheme was defined to be a separated prescheme. The term prescheme has fallen out of use, but can still be found in older books, such as Grothendieck's "Éléments de géométrie algébrique" and Mumford's "Red Book".[9] The sheaf properties of mean that its elements, which are not necessarily functions, can neverthess be patched together from their restrictions in the same way as functions.
A basic example of an affine scheme is affine -space over a field , for a natural number . By definition, is the spectrum of the polynomial ring . In the spirit of scheme theory, affine -space can in fact be defined over any commutative ring , meaning .
Schemes form a category, with morphisms defined as morphisms of locally ringed spaces. (See also: morphism of schemes.) For a scheme Y, a scheme X over Y (or a Y-scheme) means a morphism X → Y of schemes. A scheme X over a commutative ring R means a morphism X → Spec(R).
An algebraic variety over a field k can be defined as a scheme over k with certain properties. There are different conventions about exactly which schemes should be called varieties. One standard choice is that a variety over k means an integral separated scheme of finite type over k.[10]
A morphism f: X → Y of schemes determines a pullback homomorphism on the rings of regular functions, f*: O(Y) → O(X). In the case of affine schemes, this construction gives a one-to-one correspondence between morphisms Spec(A) → Spec(B) of schemes and ring homomorphisms B → A.[11] In this sense, scheme theory completely subsumes the theory of commutative rings.
Since Z is an initial object in the category of commutative rings, the category of schemes has Spec(Z) as a terminal object.
For a scheme X over a commutative ring R, an R-point of X means a section of the morphism X → Spec(R). One writes X(R) for the set of R-points of X. In examples, this definition reconstructs the old notion of the set of solutions of the defining equations of X with values in R. When R is a field k, X(k) is also called the set of k-rational points of X.
More generally, for a scheme X over a commutative ring R and any commutative R-algebra S, an S-point of X means a morphism Spec(S) → X over R. One writes X(S) for the set of S-points of X. (This generalizes the old observation that given some equations over a field k, one can consider the set of solutions of the equations in any field extension E of k.) For a scheme X over R, the assignment S ↦ X(S) is a functor from commutative R-algebras to sets. It is an important observation that a scheme X over R is determined by this functor of points.[12]
The fiber product of schemes always exists. That is, for any schemes X and Z with morphisms to a scheme Y, the categorical fiber product exists in the category of schemes. If X and Z are schemes over a field k, their fiber product over Spec(k) may be called the product X × Z in the category of k-schemes. For example, the product of affine spaces and over k is affine space over k.
Since the category of schemes has fiber products and also a terminal object Spec(Z), it has all finite limits.
Here and below, all the rings considered are commutative.
Let be an algebraically closed field. The affine space is the algebraic variety of all points with coordinates in ; its coordinate ring is the polynomial ring . The corresponding scheme is a topological space with the Zariski topology, whose closed points are the maximal ideals , the set of polynomials vanishing at . The scheme also contains a non-closed point for each non-maximal prime ideal , whose vanishing defines an irreducible subvariety ; the topological closure of the scheme point is the subscheme , including all the closed points of the subvariety, i.e. with , or equivalently .
The scheme has a basis of open subsets given by the complements of hypersurfaces,
for irreducible polynomials . This set is endowed with its coordinate ring of regular functions
.
This induces a unique sheaf which gives the usual ring of rational functions regular on a given open set .
Each ring element , a polynomial function on , also defines a function on the points of the scheme whose value at lies in the quotient ring , the residue ring. We define as the image of under the natural map . A maximal ideal gives the residue field , with the natural isomorphism , so that corresponds to the original value .
The vanishing locus of a polynomial is a hypersurface subvariety , corresponding to the principal ideal . The corresponding scheme is , a closed subscheme of affine space. For example, taking to be the complex or real numbers, the equation defines a nodal cubic curve in the affine plane , corresponding to the scheme .
The ring of integers can be considered as the coordinate ring of the scheme . The Zariski topology has closed points , the principal ideals of the prime numbers ; as well as the generic point , the zero ideal, whose closure is the whole scheme. Closed sets are finite sets, and open sets are their complements, the cofinite sets; any infinite set of points is dense.
The basis open set corresponding to the irreducible element is , with coordinate ring . For the open set , this induces .
A number corresponds to a function on the scheme , a function whose value at lies in the residue field , the finite field of integers modulo : the function is defined by , and also in the generic residue ring . The function is determined by its values at the points only, so we can think of as a kind of "regular function" on the closed points, a very special type among the arbitrary functions with .
Note that the point is the vanishing locus of the function , the point where the value of is equal to zero in the residue field. The field of "rational functions" on is the fraction field of the generic residue ring, . A fraction has "poles" at the points corresponding to prime divisors of the denominator.
This also gives a geometric interpretaton of Bezout's lemma stating that if the integers have no common prime factor, then there are integers with . Geometrically, this is a version of the weak Hilbert Nullstellensatz for the scheme : if the functions have no common vanishing points in , then they generate the unit ideal in the coordinate ring . Indeed, we may consider the terms as forming a kind of partition of unity subordinate to the covering of by the open sets .
The affine space is a variety with coordinate ring , the polynomials with integer coefficients. The corresponding scheme is , whose points are all of the prime ideals . The closed points are maximal ideals of the form , where is a prime number, and is a non-constant polynomial with no integer factor and which is irreducible modulo . Thus, we may picture as two-dimensional, with a "characteristic direction" measured by the coordinate , and a "spatial direction" with coordinate .
A given prime number defines a "vertical line", the subscheme of the prime ideal : this contains for all , the "characteristic points" of the scheme. Fixing the -coordinate, we have the "horizontal line" , the subscheme of the prime ideal . We also have the line corresponding to the rational coordinate , which does not intersect for those which divide .
A higher degree "horizontal" subscheme like corresponds to -values which are roots of , namely . This behaves differently under different -coordinates. At , we get two points , since . At , we get one ramified double-point , since . And at , we get that is a prime ideal corresponding to in an extension field of ; since we cannot distinguish between these values (they are symmetric under the Galois group), we should picture as two fused points. Overall, is a kind of fusion of two Galois-symmetric horizonal lines, a curve of degree 2.
The residue field at is , a field extension of adjoining a root of ; this is a finite field with elements, . A polynomial corresponds to a function on the scheme with values , that is . Again each is determined by its values at closed points; is the vanishing locus of the constant polynomial ; and contains the points in each characteristic corresponding to Galois orbits of roots of in the algebraic closure .
The scheme is not proper, so that pairs of curves may fail to intersect with the expected multiplicity. This is a major obstacle to analyzing Diophantine equations with geometric tools. Arakelov theory overcomes this obstacle by compactifying affine arithmetic schemes, adding points at infinity corresponding to valuations.
If we consider a polynomial then the affine scheme has a canonical morphism to and is called an arithmetic surface. The fibers are then algebraic curves over the finite fields . If is an elliptic curve, then the fibers over its discriminant locus, where are all singular schemes.[13] For example, if is a prime number and then its discriminant is . This curve is singular over the prime numbers .
This section needs expansion. You can help by adding to it. (March 2024) |
It is also fruitful to consider examples of morphisms as examples of schemes since they demonstrate their technical effectiveness for encapsulating many objects of study in algebraic and arithmetic geometry.
Here are some of the ways in which schemes go beyond older notions of algebraic varieties, and their significance.
A central part of scheme theory is the notion of coherent sheaves, generalizing the notion of (algebraic) vector bundles. For a scheme X, one starts by considering the abelian category of OX-modules, which are sheaves of abelian groups on X that form a module over the sheaf of regular functions OX. In particular, a module M over a commutative ring R determines an associated OX-module on X = Spec(R). A quasi-coherent sheaf on a scheme X means an OX-module that is the sheaf associated to a module on each affine open subset of X. Finally, a coherent sheaf (on a Noetherian scheme X, say) is an OX-module that is the sheaf associated to a finitely generated module on each affine open subset of X.
Coherent sheaves include the important class of vector bundles, which are the sheaves that locally come from finitely generated free modules. An example is the tangent bundle of a smooth variety over a field. However, coherent sheaves are richer; for example, a vector bundle on a closed subscheme Y of X can be viewed as a coherent sheaf on X that is zero outside Y (by the direct image construction). In this way, coherent sheaves on a scheme X include information about all closed subschemes of X. Moreover, sheaf cohomology has good properties for coherent (and quasi-coherent) sheaves. The resulting theory of coherent sheaf cohomology is perhaps the main technical tool in algebraic geometry.[18][19]
Considered as its functor of points, a scheme is a functor that is a sheaf of sets for the Zariski topology on the category of commutative rings, and that, locally in the Zariski topology, is an affine scheme. This can be generalized in several ways. One is to use the étale topology. Michael Artin defined an algebraic space as a functor that is a sheaf in the étale topology and that, locally in the étale topology, is an affine scheme. Equivalently, an algebraic space is the quotient of a scheme by an étale equivalence relation. A powerful result, the Artin representability theorem, gives simple conditions for a functor to be represented by an algebraic space.[20]
A further generalization is the idea of a stack. Crudely speaking, algebraic stacks generalize algebraic spaces by having an algebraic group attached to each point, which is viewed as the automorphism group of that point. For example, any action of an algebraic group G on an algebraic variety X determines a quotient stack [X/G], which remembers the stabilizer subgroups for the action of G. More generally, moduli spaces in algebraic geometry are often best viewed as stacks, thereby keeping track of the automorphism groups of the objects being classified.
Grothendieck originally introduced stacks as a tool for the theory of descent. In that formulation, stacks are (informally speaking) sheaves of categories.[21] From this general notion, Artin defined the narrower class of algebraic stacks (or "Artin stacks"), which can be considered geometric objects. These include Deligne–Mumford stacks (similar to orbifolds in topology), for which the stabilizer groups are finite, and algebraic spaces, for which the stabilizer groups are trivial. The Keel–Mori theorem says that an algebraic stack with finite stabilizer groups has a coarse moduli space that is an algebraic space.
Another type of generalization is to enrich the structure sheaf, bringing algebraic geometry closer to homotopy theory. In this setting, known as derived algebraic geometry or "spectral algebraic geometry", the structure sheaf is replaced by a homotopical analog of a sheaf of commutative rings (for example, a sheaf of E-infinity ring spectra). These sheaves admit algebraic operations that are associative and commutative only up to an equivalence relation. Taking the quotient by this equivalence relation yields the structure sheaf of an ordinary scheme. Not taking the quotient, however, leads to a theory that can remember higher information, in the same way that derived functors in homological algebra yield higher information about operations such as tensor product and the Hom functor on modules.