Propositional calculus or Sentential calculus is a calculus that represents the logical structure of truth-functional connectives ("not," "and," "or," "if…, then...," and others); the connectives such that their meanings determine the truth-value of a given sentence in which they occur once the truth-values of all the simple sentences in the given sentence are given. It is often referred to as Propositional logic.
Consider the following argument:
The truth-values, truth or falsity, of the sentences in this argument are exclusively dependent on whether each of the simple sentences in the sentences, "Jack is innocent," "Jack has an alibi," and "Jack is a murderer" is true or false. In other words, once the truth-values of the simple sentences are determined, the complex sentences in the arguments are determined only in terms of the meanings of the connectives, “if…then...,” “not,” and “and,” which are examples of truth-functional connectives. Propositional calculus, focusing on connectives of such kinds, clarifies what form a given argument (such as the one in question here) has, and studies how the correctness or incorrectness of depends on the truth-functional connectives that it contains.
The language of propositional calculus consists of propositional variables, truth-functional connectives, (most familiar ones are ) and parentheses. Formulas are built up from propositional variables by using truth-functional connectives and parentheses.
To propositional variables, either truth or falsity is assigned and, relative to the truth-value assignment, the truth-value of an arbitrary well-formed formula (for the definition, see the section Syntax) that contains the propositional variables is calculated based on the truth-functional connectives in the well-formed formula.
A propositional calculus has a set of axioms (possibly empty) and rules of inference. There are various kinds of propositional calculi, for which the soundness and completeness can be proved. (for the definitions of soundness and completeness, see the corresponding section Soundness and Completeness)
Some sentences have truth-values, truth or falsity, (declarative sentences are typical examples) and some do not (interrogative sentences, exclamatory sentences, and others). The sentences of the latter kind are excluded from what propositional calculus studies. Thus, in propositional calculus, it is assumed that every sentence is either true or false. (This assumption is called the principle of bivalence.)
Among such sentences, the sentences that do not include sentential connectives such as "and," "or," and others. (e.g. “John is a bachelor.”) are called atomic sentences. More complex sentences (e.g. “John is a bachelor and Ben is married”) are built from atomic sentences and sentential connectives.
Some sentential connectives determine the truth-values of the complex sentences in which they occur, once the truth-values of atomic sentences that the complex sentences contain are determined. For instance, the truth-value of “John is a bachelor and Ben is married” is determined purely by the meaning of the connective “and” once the truth-values of the two atomic sentences “John is a bachelor” and “Ben is married” are determined. The connectives of such a kind is called truth-functional. (Notice that this does not apply to all the sentential connectives. Consider “Ben is happy because Ben is married.” The truth-value of this sentence is still undetermined even if both the atomic sentences in this sentence are true.) Truth-functional connectives are the connectives that propositional calculus studies. Examples of such connectives are "and," "or," "if…then..." (These connectives of a certain use only. Some uses of the connectives are not truth-functional. For instance, consider counterfactual statements).
The language of propositional calculus consists of 1. propositional variables, usually annotated by p, q, r,…, 2. truth-functional connectives, , and 3. parentheses “(“ and “).” Propositional variables represent atomic sentences and , and are usually considered as “not,” “and,” “or,” “if…then...,” and “...if and only if...” respectively. is called unary (meaning that it is attachable to one wff. For the definitnion of wffs, see below.) and the other four connectives are called binary (meaning that they combine two wffs). Parentheses are used to represent the punctuations in sentences.
Well-formed formulas (wffs) are recursively built in the following way.
Conventionally the outermost set of parentheses is dropped. Also, the order of strength in which propositional connectives bind is stipulated as: and . Therefore, taking these two conventions into account, say, the wff “” built up by the above definition is written as “.”
The connective in a given wff that binds last is called the main connective of . Thus, in the case of , the main connective is . Wffs with and as their main connectives are called negation, conjunction, disjunction, conditional, and biconditional respectively.
An argument consists of a set of wffs and a distinguished wff. The wffs of the former kind are called premises and the distinguished wff is called the conclusion. The set of premises of a given argument can possibly be empty.
For instance, the set of sentences about Jack in the opening example is represented in the language of propositional logic as follows:
where p, q, and r represent “Jack is innocent,” “Jack has an alibi,” and “Jack is a murderer,” respectively. The first two wffs are the premises and the last wff is the conclusion of the argument.
Every wff in propositional calculus gets either of the two truth-values, True and False (T and F). Relative to the assignment V of truth-values to propositional variables (a function from the set of propositional variables to {T, F}, the truth-values of other wffs are determined recursively as follows:
For instance, when p, q, and r get T, T and F respectively, gets F. For the left side of the biconditional is T because p is T and is F, and the right side is F because r is F and q is T.
A wff that gets T no matter what truth-value assignment is given is called a tautology. A set of wffs (maybe empty) implies a wff if and only if is T relative to every truth-value assignment V that assigns Ts to all the wffs in . An argument, consisting of a set of wffs and a wff , is said to be valid if implies . (For instance, readers are invited to check that the argument about Jack is valid.)
If an argument, consisting of a premise set and a conclusion , is valid, , we write “,” which often reads as “ implies .” (For the left hand side of “,” the wffs in are written with commas between them, e.g. if is {p, q, r}, we write “p, q, r .”)
Propositional calculus consists of a set of specified wff called axioms (the set can possibly be empty) and rules of inference. A proof of an argument is a sequence of wffs in which (1) each wff is a premise, an axiom, or a wff that is derived from previous wffs in the sequence by a rule of inference and (2) the last wff of the sequence is the conclusion of the argument. If an argument, consisting of a premise set and a conclusion , has a proof, we write “,” which reads as “ is provable from .” (The convention for the left hand side of “” is the same as the one for “”.)
Particularly, if there is a proof for an argument with an empty set of premises, i.e. if the conclusion of the argument can be derived only from axioms based on the rules of inference, then the conclusion is called a theorem. Thus, if is a theorem, we can write “,” which reads as “ is a theorem.”
There are various propositional calculi, of which two of the most famous ones are provided below.
One famous deductive system takes the language of propositional calculus that consists of propositional variables, the connectives, and , and parentheses. The other connectives are defined as follows:
The axioms have one of the following forms:
The only rule of inference is modus ponens, i.e. from and , derive .
Here is an example of a proof in this system for [1]:
Number | wff | Justification |
---|---|---|
1 | A premiss | |
2 | A premise | |
3 | An axiom of the form A1 | |
4 | From 1 and 3 by modus ponens | |
5 | From 2 and 4 by modus ponens | |
6 | An axiom of the form A2 | |
7 | From 5 and 6 by modus ponens | |
8 | From 4 and 7 by modus ponens |
Another example takes the language of propositional calculus that consists of propositional variables, the connectives, and parentheses. The set of axioms is empty. However, it has the following rules of inference:
Here is an example of a proof in this system again for .
Number | wff | Justification |
---|---|---|
1 | A premise | |
2 | A premise | |
3 | An assumption for a conditional proof | |
4 | Iteration of 1 | |
5 | From 3 and 4 by a conditional proof | |
6 | From 2 and 5 by modus ponens | |
7 | Assumption for a conditional proof | |
8 | From 6 and 7 by modus ponens | |
9 | From 1 and 8 by modus ponens | |
10 | From 7 and 9 by a conditional proof |
Here are some of the most famous forms of arguments that are provable in both of the calculi:
Basic and Derived Argument Forms | ||
---|---|---|
Name | Sequent | Description |
Modus Ponens | ((p → q) ∧ p) ├ q | if p then q; p; therefore q |
Modus Tollens | ((p → q) ∧ ¬q) ├ ¬p | if p then q; not q; therefore not p |
Hypothetical Syllogism | ((p → q) ∧ (q → r)) ├ (p → r) | if p then q; if q then r; therefore, if p then r |
Disjunctive Syllogism | ((p ∨ q) ∧ ¬p) ├ q | Either p or q; not p; therefore, q |
Constructive Dilemma | ((p → q) ∧ (r → s) ∧ (p ∨ r)) ├ (q ∨ s) | If p then q; and if r then s; but either p or r; therefore either q or s |
Destructive Dilemma | ((p → q) ∧ (r → s) ∧ (¬q ∨ ¬s)) ├ (¬p ∨ ¬r) | If p then q; and if r then s; but either not q or not s; therefore either not p or not r |
Simplification | (p ∧ q) ├ p | p and q are true; therefore p is true |
Conjunction | p, q ├ (p ∧ q) | p and q are true separately; therefore they are true conjointly |
Addition | p ├ (p ∨ q) | p is true; therefore the disjunction (p or q) is true |
Composition | ((p → q) ∧ (p → r)) ├ (p → (q ∧ r)) | If p then q; and if p then r; therefore if p is true then q and r are true |
De Morgan's Theorem (1) | ¬(p ∧ q) ├ (¬p ∨ ¬q) | The negation of (p and q) is equiv. to (not p or not q) |
De Morgan's Theorem (2) | ¬(p ∨ q) ├ (¬p ∧ ¬q) | The negation of (p or q) is equiv. to (not p and not q) |
Commutation (1) | (p ∨ q) ├ (q ∨ p) | (p or q) is equiv. to (q or p) |
Commutation (2) | (p ∧ q) ├ (q ∧ p) | (p and q) is equiv. to (q and p) |
Association (1) | (p ∨ (q ∨ r)) ├ ((p ∨ q) ∨ r) | p or (q or r) is equiv. to (p or q) or r |
Association (2) | (p ∧ (q ∧ r)) ├ ((p ∧ q) ∧ r) | p and (q and r) is equiv. to (p and q) and r |
Distribution (1) | (p ∧ (q ∨ r)) ├ ((p ∧ q) ∨ (p ∧ r)) | p and (q or r) is equiv. to (p and q) or (p and r) |
Distribution (2) | (p ∨ (q ∧ r)) ├ ((p ∨ q) ∧ (p ∨ r)) | p or (q and r) is equiv. to (p or q) and (p or r) |
Double Negation | p ├ ¬¬p | p is equivalent to the negation of not p |
Transposition | (p → q) ├ (¬q → ¬p) | If p then q is equiv. to if not q then not p |
Material Implication | (p → q) ├ (¬p ∨ q) | If p then q is equiv. to either not p or q |
Material Equivalence (1) | (p ↔ q) ├ ((p → q) ∧ (q → p)) | (p is equiv. to q) means, (if p is true then q is true) and (if q is true then p is true) |
Material Equivalence (2) | (p ↔ q) ├ ((p ∧ q) ∨ (¬q ∧ ¬p)) | (p is equiv. to q) means, either (p and q are true) or ( both p and q are false) |
Exportation | ((p ∧ q) → r) ├ (p → (q → r)) | from (if p and q are true then r is true) we can prove (if q is true then r is true, if p is true) |
Importation | (p → (q → r)) ├ ((p ∧ q) → r) | |
Tautology | p ├ (p ∨ p) | p is true is equiv. to p is true or p is true |
Tertium non datur (Law of Excluded Middle) | ├ (p ∨ ¬ p) | p or not p is true |
A calculus is sound if, for all and implies . A calculus is complete if, for all and , implies .
There are various sound and complete propositional calculi (i.e. the calculi in which the notion of proof and that of validity correspond). The two calculi above are the examples of sound and complete propositional calculi.
All links retrieved December 1, 2022.
New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:
The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:
Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.